back to top
Wednesday, December 11, 2024
20.4 C
Sydney

The ethical dangers and opportunities in COVID-19 decision-making

Most read

New York health care workers use cell phones to record a joint flyover by the US Navy’s Blue Angels and the US Air Force’s Thunderbirds on 28 April 2020. The teams were saluting New York-area medical personnel, first responders and other front-line workers placing themselves in harm’s way during the COVID-19 pandemic. Photo: CNS, Gregory Shemitz

The COVID-19 pandemic challenges all of us in multiple ways, as individuals, families, communities, societies and a world. Some of us face additional challenges, for instance, healthcare workers and those providing essential services, who voluntarily risk infection, and those with special responsibilities, in particular, our governments and health and social policy decision-makers.

How ethics should govern the COVID-19 decision-making

As an ethicist, I have been receiving many enquiries about the ethics that should govern COVID-19 decision-making. I give a few examples below.

First, however, let us note that this is a situation where we can start our conversation from agreement, rather than disagreement, as is more common in ethics discussions. Because we are all at risk and want to protect everyone and stop the harm of this horrible virus, we can have an experience of all belonging to the same moral universe – “we’re all in this together”.

- Advertisement -

Variances in ethical decision-making

Conclusions as to the ethics that should govern COVID-19 decisions can vary depending on the level of the decision-making, that is whether it is at the individual, institutional or societal level. For example, an individual doctor has a “primary ethical obligation of personal care to each patient” and must put that patient’s “best interests” first.

A hospital must take into account the “best interests” of all patients which means they must consider just allocation of resources and efficiency and effectiveness of their use. A government has even wider considerations to incorporate in its decision-making, but especially protection of vulnerable people and maintaining the “common good”.

Conclusions as to the ethics that should govern COVID-19 decisions can vary depending on the level of the decision-making.

Good facts are necessary for good ethics and, indeed, for good law. Sometimes facts are unavoidably uncertain so we need to develop an “ethics of dealing with uncertainty”. That requires, at the least, transparency and honesty, admitting one’s errors and having the courage to say, “I don’t know” when that is the case, even though it might be pounced on by an opponent to gain political points.

These are not situations for political campaigning and I believe Australian politicians have set a good example in this regard. Excuses for lack of honesty and transparency such as “we mustn’t panic the public” are unacceptable. As the public, however, we must not demand honesty and transparency and then wrongfully punish our leaders for complying with those requirements when we do not like what we hear.

President Donald Trump talks to reporters at the White House. We need transparency and honesty, writes Australian ethicist Margaret Somerville, admitting one’s errors and having the courage to say, “I don’t know” when that is the case. It should not be a time for political campaigning. Photo: CNS, Jonathan Ernst, Reuters.

COVID-19 can face us with what is called in ethics “a world of competing sorrows”, which means there is no “no harm” option available and the choice is whom to harm. Two people needing a ventilator to have the best chance of surviving COVID-19 and only one ventilator being available or all the ventilators are already in use are examples of such situations.

Who should receive the one ventilator? Should a person be taken off a ventilator to make one available for another person? In either case, who should decide? On what basis? These are vexed and very difficult ethical issues.

Sometimes facts are unavoidably uncertain so we need to develop an “ethics of dealing with uncertainty”.

There have been instances in other countries of setting an age limit on ventilator support for people with COVID-19, even as low as 65 years old, but more often over 80. This is discrimination purely based on age, which is both ethically wrong and possibly legally actionable.

That said, it is also true that even with treatment elderly people have a worse prognosis for surviving COVID-19 infection, than the vast majority of younger people and assessment of the likely benefit of any given treatment to a given person is always a valid consideration in allocating medical resources, especially when not all people can be treated.

Care needs to be taken that a valid consideration – such as a likely lack of medical benefit for an elderly person as compared with a younger one, or for a person with a disability – is not used as a cover for unethical discrimination based on age or disability. We have seen this occur in other scarce medical resources allocation situations, for example, organs for transplantation.

Vice-Chancellor Professor Francis Campbell from The University of Notre Dame Australia explains that solidarity and honesty will get society through COVID-19. 

The need for treatment is an ethically valid consideration. We should give preference to those most in need. As well, social justice demands a preference in favour of the most disadvantaged, most vulnerable members of our community. At present in Australia that would include many people in aged care or nursing homes. Although no fault might be involved, it is beyond horrific, as has happened in NSW, to think of elderly people being “locked in” a facility where COVID-19 is circulating and their seeing their co-residents die.

We need “ethics preparedness”, which can include guidelines or policies listing ethically valid considerations – or even identifying ethically invalid ones – to guide decision-making regarding COVID-19 at all levels.

We need “ethics preparedness”, which can include guidelines or policies listing ethically valid considerations – or even identifying ethically invalid ones – to guide decision-making regarding COVID-19 at all levels, but, in my view, it is unethical to have a predetermined policy, which would automatically exclude some people from treatment.

In short, each case must be considered individually and on its merits in making a decision regarding access to medical treatment, especially when it involves the allocation of life-saving resources. Moreover, simply following policies or guidelines does not automatically guarantee either the ethical validity of decisions or legal immunity for them. In such situations. we should also ask who and what decisions are responsible for the shortage of resources.

We should give preference to those most in need, the disadvantaged. More recently there are elderly people being “locked in” a facility where COVID-19 is circulating and their seeing their co-residents die.

The COVID-19 pandemic raises a multitude of difficult ethical issues relating to care for individual patients and their families; risks for healthcare professionals; coping of healthcare systems; complex health and public policy decisions for Government, including regarding international relationships, economic fallout, and so on. What we decide in relation to dealing with COVID-19 will have impact well beyond healthcare and our national borders and far into the future.

Related

Rebecca Gosper: Towards the elderly we are acting like schizophrenics
Catholic healthcare workers on the COVID-19 frontline
Ethics for Australian healthcare in the midst of a pandemic

- Advertisement -
- Advertisement -